This theory does not contain any formalized mathematics used in other theories, but is an introduction to IsarMathLib project.
Isar (the Isabelle's formal proof language) was designed to be similar to the standard language of mathematics. Any person able to read proofs in a typical mathematical paper should be able to read and understand Isar proofs without having to learn a special proof language. However, Isar is a formal proof language and as such it does contain a couple of constructs whose meaning is hard to guess. In this tutorial we will define a notion and prove an example theorem about that notion, explaining Isar syntax along the way. This tutorial may also serve as a style guide for IsarMathLib contributors. Note that this tutorial aims to help in reading the presentation of the Isar language that is used in IsarMathLib proof document and HTML rendering on the FormalMath.org site, but does not teach how to write proofs that can be verified by Isabelle. This presentation is different than the source processed by Isabelle (the concept that the source and presentation look different should be familiar to any LaTeX user). To learn how to write Isar proofs one needs to study the source of this tutorial as well.
The first thing that mathematicians typically do is to define notions. In Isar this is done with the definition keyword. In our case we define a notion of two sets being disjoint. We will use the infix notation, i.e. the string \( \text{ is disjoint with } \) put between two sets to denote our notion of disjointness. The left side of the \( \equiv \) symbol is the notion being defined, the right side says how we define it. In Isabelle/ZF 0 is used to denote both zero (of natural numbers) and the empty set, which is not surprising as those two things are the same in set theory.
definition
\( A \text{ is disjoint with } B \equiv A \cap B = 0 \)
We are ready to prove a theorem. Here we show that the relation of being disjoint is symmetric. We start with one of the keywords ''theorem'', ''lemma'' or ''corollary''. In Isar they are synonymous. Then we provide a name for the theorem. In standard mathematics theorems are numbered. In Isar we can do that too, but it is considered better to give theorems meaningful names. After the ''shows'' keyword we give the statement to show. The \( \longleftrightarrow \) symbol denotes the equivalence in Isabelle/ZF. Here we want to show that "A is disjoint with B iff and only if B is disjoint with A". To prove this fact we show two implications - the first one that \( A \text{ is disjoint with } B \) implies \( B \text{ is disjoint with } A \) and then the converse one. Each of these implications is formulated as a statement to be proved and then proved in a subproof like a mini-theorem. Each subproof uses a proof block to show the implication. Proof blocks are delimited with curly brackets in Isar. Proof block is one of the constructs that does not exist in informal mathematics, so it may be confusing. When reading a proof containing a proof block I suggest to focus first on what is that we are proving in it. This can be done by looking at the first line or two of the block and then at the last statement. In our case the block starts with "assume \( A \text{ is disjoint with } B \) and the last statement is "then have \( B \text{ is disjoint with } A \)". It is a typical pattern when someone needs to prove an implication: one assumes the antecedent and then shows that the consequent follows from this assumption. Implications are denoted with the \( \longrightarrow \) symbol in Isabelle. After we prove both implications we collect them using the ''moreover'' construct. The keyword ''ultimately'' indicates that what follows is the conclusion of the statements collected with ''moreover''. The ''show'' keyword is like ''have'', except that it indicates that we have arrived at the claim of the theorem (or a subproof).
theorem disjointness_symmetric:
shows \( A \text{ is disjoint with } B \longleftrightarrow B \text{ is disjoint with } A \)proofThe Fol1, ZF1 and Nat_ZF_IML theory files contain some background material that is needed for the remaining theories.
Order_ZF and Order_ZF_1a reformulate material from standard Isabelle's Order theory in terms of non-strict (less-or-equal) order relations. Order_ZF_1 on the other hand directly continues the Order theory file using strict order relations (less and not equal). This is useful for translating theorems from Metamath.
In NatOrder_ZF we prove that the usual order on natural numbers is linear. The func1 theory provides basic facts about functions. func_ZF continues this development with more advanced topics that relate to algebraic properties of binary operations, like lifting a binary operation to a function space, associative, commutative and distributive operations and properties of functions related to order relations. func_ZF_1 is about properties of functions related to order relations.
The standard Isabelle's Finite theory defines the finite powerset of a set as a certain "datatype" (?) with some recursive properties. IsarMathLib's Finite1 and Finite_ZF_1 theories develop more facts about this notion. These two theories are obsolete now. They will be gradually replaced by an approach based on set theory rather than tools specific to Isabelle. This approach is presented in Finite_ZF theory file.
In FinOrd_ZF we talk about ordered finite sets.
The EquivClass1 theory file is a reformulation of the material in the standard Isabelle's EquivClass theory in the spirit of ZF set theory. FiniteSeq_ZF discusses the notion of finite sequences (a.k.a. lists).
InductiveSeq_ZF provides the definition and properties of (what is known in basic calculus as) sequences defined by induction, i. e. by a formula of the form \(a_0 = x,\ a_{n+1} = f(a_n)\).
Fold_ZF shows how the familiar from functional programming notion of fold can be interpreted in set theory.
Partitions_ZF is about splitting a set into non-overlapping subsets. This is a common trick in proofs.
Semigroup_ZF treats the expressions of the form \(a_0\cdot a_1\cdot .. \cdot a_n\), (i.e. products of finite sequences), where "\(\cdot\)" is an associative binary operation.
CommutativeSemigroup_ZF is another take on a similar subject. This time we consider the case when the operation is commutative and the result of depends only on the set of elements we are summing (additively speaking), but not the order.
The Topology_ZF series covers basics of general topology: interior, closure, boundary, compact sets, separation axioms and continuous functions. Group_ZF, Group_ZF_1, Group_ZF_1b and Group_ZF_2 provide basic facts of the group theory. Group_ZF_3 considers the notion of almost homomorphisms that is nedeed for the real numbers construction in Real_ZF.
The TopologicalGroup connects the Topology_ZF and Group_ZF series and starts the subject of topological groups with some basic definitions and facts.
In DirectProduct_ZF we define direct product of groups and show some its basic properties.
The OrderedGroup_ZF theory treats ordered groups. This is a suprisingly large theory for such relatively obscure topic. Ring_ZF defines rings. Ring_ZF_1 covers the properties of rings that are specific to the real numbers construction in Real_ZF.
The OrderedRing_ZF theory looks at the consequences of adding a linear order to the ring algebraic structure. Field_ZF and OrderedField_ZF contain basic facts about (you guessed it) fields and ordered fields. Int_ZF_IML theory considers the integers as a monoid (multiplication) and an abelian ordered group (addition). In Int_ZF_1 we show that integers form a commutative ring. Int_ZF_2 contains some facts about slopes (almost homomorphisms on integers) needed for real numbers construction, used in Real_ZF_1.
In the IntDiv_ZF_IML theory we translate some properties of the integer quotient and reminder functions studied in the standard Isabelle's IntDiv_ZF theory to the notation used in IsarMathLib. The Real_ZF and Real_ZF_1 theories contain the construction of real numbers based on the paper \cite{Arthan2004} by R. D. Arthan (not Cauchy sequences, not Dedekind sections). The heavy lifting is done mostly in Group_ZF_3, Ring_ZF_1 and Int_ZF_2. Real_ZF contains the part of the construction that can be done starting from generic abelian groups (rather than additive group of integers). This allows to show that real numbers form a ring. Real_ZF_1 continues the construction using properties specific to the integers and showing that real numbers constructed this way form a complete ordered field.
Cardinal_ZF provides a couple of theorems about cardinals that are mostly used for studying properties of topological properties (yes, this is kind of meta). The main result (proven without AC) is that if two sets can be injectively mapped into an infinite cardinal, then so can be their union. There is also a definition of the Axiom of Choice specific for a given cardinal (so that the choice function exists for families of sets of given cardinality). Some properties are proven for such predicates, like that for finite families of sets the choice function always exists (in ZF) and that the axiom of choice for a larger cardinal implies one for a smaller cardinal.
Group_ZF_4 considers conjugate of subgroup and defines simple groups. A nice theorem here is that endomorphisms of an abelian group form a ring. The first isomorphism theorem (a group homomorphism \(h\) induces an isomorphism between the group divided by the kernel of \(h\) and the image of \(h\)) is proven.
Turns out given a property of a topological space one can define a local version of a property in general. This is studied in the the Topology_ZF_properties_2 theory and applied to local versions of the property of being finite or compact or Hausdorff (i.e. locally finite, locally compact, locally Hausdorff). There are a couple of nice applications, like one-point compactification that allows to show that every locally compact Hausdorff space is regular. Also there are some results on the interplay between hereditability of a property and local properties.
For a given surjection \(f : X\rightarrow Y\), where \(X\) is a topological space one can consider the weakest topology on \(Y\) which makes \(f\) continuous, let's call it a quotient topology generated by \(f\). The quotient topology generated by an equivalence relation r on X is actually a special case of this setup, where \(f\) is the natural projection of \(X\) on the quotient \(X/r\). The properties of these two ways of getting new topologies are studied in Topology_ZF_8 theory. The main result is that any quotient topology generated by a function is homeomorphic to a topology given by an equivalence relation, so these two approaches to quotient topologies are kind of equivalent.
As we all know, automorphisms of a topological space form a group. This fact is proven in Topology_ZF_9 and the automorphism groups for co-cardinal, included-set, and excluded-set topologies are identified. For order topologies it is shown that order isomorphisms are homeomorphisms of the topology induced by the order. Properties preserved by continuous functions are studied and as an application it is shown for example that quotient topological spaces of compact (or connected) spaces are compact (or connected, resp.) The Topology_ZF_10 theory is about products of two topological spaces. It is proven that if two spaces are \(T_0\) (or \(T_1\), \(T_2\), regular, connected) then their product is as well.
Given a total order on a set one can define a natural topology on it generated by taking the rays and intervals as the base. The Topology_ZF_11 theory studies relations between the order and various properties of generated topology. For example one can show that if the order topology is connected, then the order is complete (in the sense that for each set bounded from above the set of upper bounds has a minimum). For a given cardinal \(\kappa\) we can consider generalized notion of \(\kappa-separability\). Turns out \(\kappa\)-separability is related to (order) density of sets of cardinality \(\kappa\) for order topologies.
Being a topological group imposes additional structure on the topology of the group, in particular its separation properties. In Topological_Group_ZF_1.thy theory it is shown that if a topology is \(T_0\), then it must be \(T_3\) , and that the topology in a topological group is always regular.
For a given normal subgroup of a topological group we can define a topology on the quotient group in a natural way. At the end of the Topological_Group_ZF_2.thy theory it is shown that such topology on the quotient group makes it a topological group.
The Topological_Group_ZF_3.thy theory studies the topologies on subgroups of a topological group. A couple of nice basic properties are shown, like that the closure of a subgroup is a subgroup, closure of a normal subgroup is normal and, a bit more surprising (to me) property that every locally-compact subgroup of a \(T_0\) group is closed.
In Complex_ZF we construct complex numbers starting from a complete ordered field (a model of real numbers). We also define the notation for writing about complex numbers and prove that the structure of complex numbers constructed there satisfies the axioms of complex numbers used in Metamath.
MMI_prelude defines the mmisar0 context in which most theorems translated from Metamath are proven. It also contains a chapter explaining how the translation works.
In the Metamath_interface theory we prove a theorem that the mmisar0 context is valid (can be used) in the complex0 context. All theories using the translated results will import the Metamath_interface theory. The Metamath_sampler theory provides some examples of using the translated theorems in the complex0 context.
The theories MMI_logic_and_sets, MMI_Complex, MMI_Complex_1 and MMI_Complex_2 contain the theorems imported from the Metamath's set.mm database. As the translated proofs are rather verbose these theories are not printed in this proof document. The full list of translated facts can be found in the Metamath_theorems.txt file included in the IsarMathLib distribution. The MMI_examples provides some theorems imported from Metamath that are printed in this proof document as examples of how translated proofs look like.